Pablo Muchnik has a very interesting book and a fascinating
take on this controversial subject matter in Kant. I now understand the concept of radical evil in Kant much
better.
Muchnik, in his book Kant’s
Theory of Evil, clarifies the issues involved in Kant’s doctrine of radical
evil. He steers a course between
Henry Allison and Allen Wood by showing that the idea that human beings have a
tendency to evil is not just an empirical observation but also has a priori
status.
Muchnik shows us that Kant explicates the radical tendency
to evil in the notions of the frailty of the human heart, the impurity of the
human heart and finally the wickedness of the human heart. The frailty of the human heart is
referred to in the concept of the “weakness of the will.” St. Paul complained that what he willed
to do, he did not do, and what he willed not to do that is what he did (Romans
7). The agent knows the action is
morally required, but fails to carry it out and instead acts out of
inclination. In this
case, Muchnik argues, the agent acknowledges the validity of the moral law, but
doesn’t grant it authority. He
says “The agent with a weak heart, then makes herself believe that her
motivational structure is essentially good, even when her actions suggest
otherwise” (p. 157). He holds that
the agent with a frail heart is tempted by “gluttony, lust, and wild
lawlessness [in relation to other human beings]” even in the case where moral
luck makes her moderate and sympathetic.
The frail heart knows better but doesn’t do better, but the
impure heart doesn’t adopt the moral law as a sufficient incentive for moral
action but allows incentives of the inclinations to determine her actions. Her actions conform to duty, but are
not done purely from duty.
Her real motivation is self-love even if she looks like she is doing the
moral thing. Muchnik tells us that
this agent transforms morality into a system of hypothetical imperatives.
The wicked heart represents depravity and perverts moral
judgment at its root. The wicked
heart pursues non-moral reasons as a matter of principle. She “callously uses everyone else as a
tool to her goals, justifying her conduct in terms of a perverse conception of
the good” (p. 161). Kant considers this the highest expression of the
propensity to evil. This
person systematically denies dignity to other persons and even to themselves.
Muchnik also takes a position on the sticky question of
whether Kant’s position can adequately account for the immorality of murder and
genocide. Against Claudia Card and
Bernstein, he defends Kant’s position that even these horrific acts are
motivated by self love. Bernstein
wants to rehabilitate the idea of the diabolical will, but Muchnik argues that
such a will would be incapable of being legislative and would undermine itself.
No comments:
Post a Comment